Quotations from Symbolic Speech Cases
Stromberg v. California (1931):
Section 403-a of the California Penal Code
provided:
"Any person who displays a red flag, banner or badge
or any flag, badge, banner, or device of any color or form
whatever in any public place or in any meeting
place or public assembly, or from or on any house,
building or window as a sign, symbol or emblem of
opposition to organized government or as an invitation
or stimulus to anarchistic action or as an aid to propaganda
that is of a seditious character is guilty of a felony."
West Virginia v. Barnette (1943):
“There is no doubt that, in connection with the
pledges, the flag salute is a form of utterance. Symbolism
is a primitive but effective way of communicating ideas. The
use of an emblem or flag to symbolize some system, idea,
institution, or personality, is a short cut from mind to
mind. Causes and nations, political parties, lodges and
ecclesiastical groups seek to knit the loyalty of their
followings to a flag or banner, a color or design. The State
announces rank, function, and authority through crowns and
maces, uniforms and black robes; the church speaks through
the Cross, the Crucifix, the altar and shrine, and clerical
raiment. Symbols of State often convey political ideas just
as religious symbols come to convey theological ones.
Associated with many of these symbols are appropriate
gestures of acceptance or respect: a salute, a bowed or
bared head, a bended knee. A person gets from a symbol the
meaning he puts into it, and what is one man's comfort and
inspiration is another's jest and scorn.”
United States v. O'Brien (1968):
"We cannot accept the view that an apparently
limitless variety of conduct can be labeled 'speech'
whenever the person engaging in the conduct intends thereby
to express an idea. However, even on the assumption that the
alleged communicative element in O'Brien's conduct is
sufficient to bring into play the First Amendment, it does
not necessarily follow that the destruction of a
registration certificate is constitutionally protected
activity. This Court has held that, when 'speech' and
'nonspeech' elements are combined in the same course of
conduct, a sufficiently important governmental interest in
regulating the nonspeech element can justify incidental
limitations on First Amendment freedoms."
O'Brien Test:
“[A] government regulation is sufficiently
justified if it is within the constitutional power of the
Government; if it furthers an important or substantial
governmental interest; if the governmental interest is
unrelated to the suppression of free expression; and if the
incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms
is no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that
interest.”
Spence v. Washington (1974):
Wash. Rev. Code § 9.86.020. This statute provides,
in pertinent part:
"No person shall, in any manner, for exhibition or display:
"(1) Place or cause to be placed any word, figure, mark,
picture, design, drawing or advertisement of any nature upon
any flag, standard, color, ensign or shield of the United
States or of this state . . . or
"(2) Expose to public view any such flag, standard, color,
ensign or shield upon which shall have been printed, painted
or otherwise produced, or to which shall have been attached,
appended, affixed or annexed any such word, figure, mark,
picture, design, drawing or advertisement . . . ."
Spence Test:
“An intent to convey a particularized message was
present, and in the surrounding circumstances the likelihood
was great that the message would be understood by those who
viewed it.”
Buckley v. Valeo (1976)
"A contribution serves as a general expression
of support for the candidate and his views, but does not
communicate the underlying basis for the support. The
quantity of communication by the contributor does not
increase perceptibly with the size of his contribution,
since the expression rests solely on the undifferentiated,
symbolic act of contributing. At most, the size of the
contribution provides a very rough index of the intensity of
the contributor's support for the candidate. A limitation on
the amount of money a person may give to a candidate or
campaign organization thus involves little direct restraint
on his political communication, for it permits the symbolic
expression of support evidenced by a contribution but does
not in any way infringe the contributor's freedom to discuss
candidates and issues."
Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of
Boston (1995):
"The protected expression that inheres
in a parade is not limited to its banners and songs,
however, for the Constitution looks beyond written or spoken
words as mediums of expression. Noting that '[s]ymbolism is
a primitive but effective way of communicating ideas,' West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v.
Barnette (1943), our cases have recognized that the
First Amendment shields such acts as saluting a flag (and
refusing to do so),
wearing an arm band to protest a war, displaying a red flag, and even '[m]arching,
walking or parading' in uniforms displaying the swastika. As some of these
examples show, a narrow, succinctly articulable message is
not a condition of constitutional protection, which if
confined to expressions conveying a 'particularized
message,' would never reach the unquestionably shielded
painting of Jackson Pollock, music of Arnold Schonberg, or
Jabberwocky verse of Lewis Carroll."
Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic and Institutional
Rights (FAIR) (2006):
"In this case, accommodating the
military’s message does not affect the law schools’ speech,
because the schools are not speaking when they host
interviews and recruiting receptions. Unlike a parade
organizer’s choice of parade contingents, a law school’s
decision to allow recruiters on campus is not inherently
expressive. Law schools facilitate recruiting to assist
their students in obtaining jobs. A law school’s recruiting
services lack the expressive quality of a parade, a
newsletter, or the editorial page of a newspaper. . . ."
"Unlike flag burning, the conduct regulated by the Solomon
Amendment is not inherently expressive. Prior to the
adoption of the Solomon Amendment’s equal-access
requirement, law schools 'expressed' their disagreement with
the military by treating military recruiters differently
from other recruiters. But these actions were expressive
only because the law schools accompanied their conduct with
speech explaining it. For example, the point of requiring
military interviews to be conducted on the undergraduate
campus is not 'overwhelmingly apparent.' An observer who
sees military recruiters interviewing away from the law
school has no way of knowing whether the law school is
expressing its disapproval of the military, all the law
school’s interview rooms are full, or the military
recruiters decided for reasons of their own that they would
rather interview someplace else. . . .
The expressive component of a law school’s actions is not
created by the conduct itself but by the speech that
accompanies it. The fact that such explanatory speech is
necessary is strong evidence that the conduct at issue here
is not so inherently expressive that it warrants protection
under O’Brien. If combining speech and conduct were enough
to create expressive conduct, a regulated party could always
transform conduct into 'speech' simply by talking about it.
For instance, if an individual announces that he intends to
express his disapproval of the Internal Revenue Service by
refusing to pay his income taxes, we would have to apply
O’Brien to determine whether the Tax Code violates the First
Amendment. Neither O’Brien nor its progeny supports such a
result.