Abrams v. United States (November 10, 1919)
Holmes, J., dissenting
But when men have realized that time has upset many fighting
faiths, they may come to believe even more than they believe the
very foundations of their own conduct that the
ultimate good desired is better reached by free trade in ideas
-- that the best test of truth is the power of the thought to
get itself accepted in the competition of the market, and that
truth is the only ground upon which their wishes safely can be
carried out. That, at any rate, is the theory of our
Constitution. It is an experiment, as all life is an
experiment. Every year, if not every day, we have to
wager our salvation upon some prophecy based upon imperfect
knowledge. While that experiment is part of our system, I
think that we should be eternally vigilant against attempts to
check the expression of opinions that we loathe and believe to
be fraught with death, unless they so imminently threaten
immediate interference with the lawful and pressing purposes
of the law that an immediate check is required to save the
country.
Only the emergency that makes it immediately dangerous to leave
the correction of evil counsels to time warrants making any
exception to the sweeping command, "Congress shall make no law .
. . abridging the freedom of speech."
Whitney v. California 274 U.S. 357 (1927)
Justice Brandeis, concurring, joined by Justice Holmes:
“Those who won our independence believed that the final end of
the state was to make men free to develop their faculties, and
that in its government the deliberative forces should prevail
over the arbitrary. They valued liberty both as an end and as a
means. They believed liberty to be the secret of happiness and
courage to be the secret of liberty. They believed that freedom
to think as you will and to speak as you think are means
indispensable to the discovery and spread of political truth;
that without free speech and assembly discussion would be
futile; that with them, discussion affords ordinarily adequate
protection against the dissemination of noxious doctrine; that
the greatest menace to freedom is an inert people; that public
discussion is a political duty; and that this should be a
fundamental principle of the American government. They
recognized the risks to which all human institutions are
subject. But they knew that order cannot be secured merely
through fear of punishment for its infraction; that it is
hazardous to discourage thought, hope and imagination; that fear
breeds repression; that repression breeds hate; that hate
menaces stable government; that the path of safety lies in the
opportunity to discuss freely supposed grievances and proposed
remedies; and that the fitting remedy for evil counsels is good
ones. Believing in the power of reason as applied through public
discussion, they eschewed silence coerced by law—the argument of
force in its worst form. Recognizing the occasional tyrannies of
governing majorities, they amended the Constitution so that free
speech and assembly should be guaranteed.
Fear of serious injury cannot alone justify suppressions of free
speech and assembly. Men feared witches and burnt women. It is
the function of speech to free men from the bondage of
irrational fears. To justify suppression of free speech there
must be reasonable ground to fear that serious evil will result
if free speech is practiced. There must be reasonable ground to
believe that the danger apprehended is imminent. There must be
reasonable ground to believe that the evil to be prevented is a
serious one. Every denunciation of existing law tends in some
measure to increase the probability that there will be violation
of it. Condonation of a breach enhances the probability.
Expressions of approval add to the probability. Propagation of
the criminal state of mind by teaching syndicalism increases it.
Advocacy of lawbreaking heightens it still further. But even
advocacy of violation, however reprehensible morally, is not a
justification for denying free speech where the advocacy falls
short of incitement and there is nothing to indicate that the
advocacy would be immediately acted on. The wide difference
between advocacy and incitement, between preparation and
attempt, between assembling and conspiracy, must be borne in
mind. In order to support a finding of clear and present danger
it must be shown either that immediate serious violence was to
be expected or was advocated, or that the past conduct furnished
reason to believe that such advocacy was then contemplated. Those who won our independence by revolution were
not cowards. They did not fear political change. They did not
exalt order at the cost of liberty. To courageous, self
reliant men, with confidence in the power of free and fearless
reasoning applied through the processes of popular government,
no danger flowing from speech can be deemed clear and present,
unless the incidence of the evil apprehended is so imminent
that it may befall before there is opportunity for full
discussion. If there be time to expose through discussion the
falsehood and fallacies, to avert the evil by the processes of
education, the remedy to be applied is more speech, not
enforced silence. Only an emergency can justify repression.
Such must be the rule if authority is to be reconciled with
freedom. Such, in my opinion, is the command of the
Constitution . . .
Moreover, even imminent danger cannot justify resort to
prohibition of these functions essential to effective democracy,
unless the evil apprehended is relatively serious. Prohibition
of free speech and assembly is a measure so stringent that it
would be inappropriate as the means for averting a relatively
trivial harm to society.”